The Character of Color Terms: A Materialist View
This paper investigates the character of predicates like:
λxy(x appears red to y),
where x stands for a visible object and y for a perceiving subject (the reference to a time
may be neglected).1 I take here ”character” in the sense of Kaplan (1977) as substantiated
by Haas-Spohn (1995 and Chapter 14 in this book)). The point of using Kaplan’s
framework is simple, but of utmost importance: It provides a scheme for clearly separating
epistemological and metaphysical issues, for specifying how the two domains are related,
and for connecting them to questions concerning meaning where confusions are often
only duplicated. All this is achieved by it better than by any alternative I know of.2
Therefore using this framework seems especially relevant to color talk where meta-
physical and epistemological issues are more difficult to tell apart or may even seem to
. And it should help in particular with my more specific goal, namely to clarify
the epistemological and metaphysical status of such statements as:
x is red if and only if x would appear red to most English-speaking people under
I am very much indebted to Wolfgang Benkewitz, Martine Nida-Rümelin, and Ulrike Haas-Spohn; to alarge extent the ideas of this paper have emerged in long lasting dicsussions with them. I am also indebtedto Galen Strawson for various helpful remarks concerning style and content. The research was supportedby grant Sp 279/4-2 of the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft.
It may seem excessively correct to use λ-abstraction here. But I do so only because it will help me
The credit equally goes to Stalnaker. In fact, the epistemological usefulness of the framework stands
out much more clearly in his work; cf. in particular Stalnaker (1978) and (1987). Despite their mutualclaims of distinctness the work of Kaplan and that of Stalnaker are so closely related that I feel justified inspeaking of one framework; for the precise nature of this relation cf. Haas-Spohn (1995, §§ 2.1, 3.9).
Almog (1981) is carried by the same enthusiasm concerning this framework. It is the only example I
know of which explicitly takes this approach to analyzing color talk. But we differ in details, as will beseen below; moreover, in (1984) Almog withdrew his theory presented in (1981) and developed a new onewithout saying, however, how it applies to color talk. x appears red to y if and only if x (appropriately) causes y to be in a neural state of
x is red if and only if the reflectance spectrum of the surface of x is of the kind R.
Indeed, I shall argue that (1) is analytic only in one reading and merely a priori in
another reading. Moreover, I shall argue that after having set aside epistemological worries
there is no good reason why one should not be able to be metaphysically conservative and
to believe that (2) and (3) are necessarily, though a posteriori true for some N and some R,
i.e., to sustain physicalism concerning colors and a type-type identity theory concerning
color experiences; this is why I have characterized my views in the title as materialistic.
Those who share these views anyway might still find it interesting to see how they fit into
a broader theoretical framework; and those who oppose these views have to face the whole
framework which appears to be successful on other scores. In any case, the framework
should help both sides to more easily locate and clarify their divergence. Indeed, it was the
main intention of this paper and the twin paper by Martine Nida-Rümelin (Chapter 16 in
this book) to exemplify this potential of clarification.
The paper starts with a presupposition and will then present six claims, the last three
being the ones about (1)-(3) I have just indicated.
What I presuppose is simply the general adequacy and power of the framework of
Kaplan and Stalnaker; I briefly recall its essentials as I use it here (cf. also Haas-Spohn,
Chapter 14 of this book). According to this framework, the right way of doing semantics
for a given natural language is to recursively specify the character of all well-formed
expressions of that language. The character of an expression is a function which assigns
to each context the intension the expression has in that context, where the intension is a
function from the set of index worlds or, more generally, from the set of indices into the
set of categorically appropriate extensions. Thus, if a possible utterance of an expression
is defined to be just that expression in a possible context, then the character of that ex-
pression may be represented by a two-dimensional scheme, the rows of which show the
intensions of all of its possible utterances.
There is wide agreement that intensions are suited for treating metaphysical modali-
ties, in particular metaphysical necessity, but also counterfactuals, causation, and so forth.
However, the two-dimensional scheme is also capable, though this is less accepted4, to
generally account for epistemological modalities, apriority, linguistically expressible belief,
Kaplan, for instance, does not fully believe in it; cf. his skeptical remarks in (1977, § XXII).
A preliminary point is that each context determines its associated index.5 Thus, each
possible utterance of an expression as such has not only an intension, but also an
extension, namely, the value of the intension at the associated index; in particular, each
utterance of a sentence has a truth value. Following Stalnaker, I call the function which
assigns to each context the extension an expression has in that context the diagonal of the
expression; this function is, so to speak, the diagonal of the two-dimensional scheme that
represents the character of the expression. It is this diagonal which does the epistemolo-
gical job. The general reason is Stalnaker’s, and it is very simple. Namely, whenever a
speaker utters a sentence or a hearer hears one, she or he is not fully informed about the
actual context; but in any case the speaker believes she says something which is true in the
context and the hearer, if he accepts the utterance, believes he hears something which is
true in the context. Thus, their epistemic attitudes are directed to possible contexts, that is,
have sets of possible contexts (or the corresponding indicator functions) as their objects6,
and it is the diagonal of the uttered sentence which represents their belief. Clearly, the
belief expressed by speaking and acquired by listening is a belief de dicto.
Consequently–and this is important–the diagonals of sentences are more specifically to be
taken to represent the corresponding beliefs de dicto (cf., however, footnote 14 below).7
If this epistemological account is to work, a crucial hypothesis is required to hold:
There is a stock of philosophical arguments showing that the intensions of sentences are
(almost) never the objects of belief.8 But for context-independent sentences having the
same intension in every context, the diagonal essentially coincides with the intension; and
clearly, sentences built from context-independent expressions are in turn context-inde-
pendent. Therefore, if the diagonal is to perform its epistemological job, most expressions
To arrive at the same conclusion in a slightly different way: A sentence is a priori
(true) if and only if its diagonal assigns truth to all possible contexts; if neither it nor its5
If an index consists only of an index world, the index associated with a context is just the world of
that context. The same holds for less simply conceived indices–as long as for each index parameter there isa corresponding context parameter (that this is so is a substantial semantic claim).
This idea is briefly indicated in Lewis (1983, 230), and further developed in Haas-Spohn (1995, chap.
As will become clear, this marks a basic difference between this paper and Nida-Rümelin (Chapter 16
of this book). Nida-Rümelin holds that in the special case of utterances of sentences like ”the sky is blue”the normal speaker expresses the phenomenal, as she calls it, as well as the nonphenomenal belief that thesky is blue; this agrees with her diverging explanation of the character of color terms. By contrast, I thinkthat also in this special case the belief primarily expressed is only the belief de dicto (which roughly,though not fully corresponds to what she calls the nonphenomenal belief), and that the ascription of anyfurther beliefs to speakers on the basis of their utterances is licensed only by additional backgroundassumptions which may or may not hold.
The best-known references are, of course, Putnam (1975), Kripke (1979), and Burge (1979).
negation is a priori true, it is a posteriori or informative. Clearly, a context-independent
sentence which is necessary in one context must also be a priori and in fact analytic, i.e.
true in all contexts and at all indices.9 However, many necessary sentences are informative
and not a priori, let alone analytic. Therefore, again, most expressions must be context-
Hence, for this hypothesis to hold true usual context dependence as in indexicals
and demonstratives is not enough. One has to interpret Putnam’s hidden indexicality of
natural kind terms as dependence on the context world as it is here understood10, and one
has to find context dependence in other predicates, for instance in Burge’s examples, and
. For the same reason it will be crucial to find out whether the color
terms (A) and (B) are hidden indexicals, i.e. dependent on the context world; this is the
only way to tell whether their metaphysics and their epistemology can be treated distinctly
So, how then do we determine the character of a given expression? First, we find out
what is known a priori about the extension of the expression; in principle, we can do this
with good old Cartesian methodical doubt. Having done this, we know the diagonal of the
expression; we thus have one entry in each row of the two-dimensional scheme. From that
entry we project the entire row, that is an extension for all of the other indices. The vehicle
for doing this is what may be called the essentiality convention pertinent to the expression.
This convention specifies for each context what is essential for the extension of the
expression and thus allows us to project it onto other indices. It must indeed be assumed
that the linguistic community has such an essentiality convention for each of its referring
A final preliminary point: My epistemological talk is quite loose in an important
respect. Usually, belief, apriority, informativity, etc. are notions applying to individual
Or, equivalently, a sentence is analytic iff its necessity is a priori. This is Kripke’s notion of analyt-
How this may be done is explained by Haas-Spohn in Chapter 14 of this book.
Kaplan was skeptical of the generality of the epistemological strategy (which he had invented for
demonstratives) precisely because he denied the context-dependence of names. And Almog withdrew his(1981) precisely because he had there misidentified the context-dependence of names; cf. Almog (1984),pp. 10f.
For details see Haas-Spohn (1995, § 3.5). However, the point is easily explained with Putnam’s
”water”-example: It is a convention of the English-speaking community that ”water” is a natural kindterm denoting a substance, if there is a single substance underlying most of what we call ”water”, or anymixture of a few substances, if there are few substances underlying most of our ”water” paradigms, oranything sharing certain superficial characteristics, if no underlying physical structure can be found. Thisis the English essentiality convention for ”water” as Putnam (1975) describes it; and the context worldthen tells which of the possible cases for which the convention is prepared becomes relevant and thuswhat is water in other possible index worlds.
subjects; something is believed by, or is informative to, a given individual. On the other
hand, I have explained a character to be that of a given natural language (or, more precisely,
of a given and maybe changing state of that language). This entails that all the epi-
stemological notions just derived from the character must be taken as applying to the given
linguistic community as a whole and not to any of its subjects; the apriori is that of the
linguistic community; informativity is measured by communal standards; etc. Such
communal epistemic states are certainly a vague matter, but not worse than meanings and
languages; and when talking about the latter, we certainly cannot avoid talking of the
There is a certain tension between the individual and the communal notions. Indeed,
the tension is irreducible, since I take the communal epistemic state not as a kind of
average of all the individual epistemic states or as something like Putnam’s stereotype,
which may be assumed to be embodied in most or all competent individuals, but rather as a
kind of sum of the individual states, as consisting of what is recognized by the community
as the best knowledge available to it, which need not be embodied in any individual. If,
nevertheless, one wants to stick to the sketched framework, the conclusion is that it has to
be doubled, i.e., to be developed on a communal as well as on an individual level, including
an explanation of how the two levels relate.13
However, all this seems unnecessarily complicated for the present purpose. There-
fore I will be deliberately sloppy concerning the two levels, or, rather, my account will
explicitly refer to the communal level while pretending–although this is, strictly speaking,
false–that it equally applies to the individual level.14 It seems to me that my account is not
essentially affected by this sloppiness; but this is a claim I do not attempt to prove here
(even though Nida-Rümelin, in Chapter 16 of this book, may throw doubt on it).
So much about the framework I am presupposing. How does all of this apply to
color talk? I shall unfold this in a series of claims:
Claim 1: Color terms like (A) λx(x is red) are hidden indexicals.
This looks implausible. Our standard example for a hidden indexical is ”water”, and at
first sight ”red” seems to be quite different from ”water”. We all might say to the very
This is elaborated in Haas-Spohn (1995, §§ 3.8, 3.9); it is here where the crucial difference between
In particular, this remark modifies my claim that the diagonal of a sentence represents the cor-
responding belief de dicto. This is correct only if ”belief de dicto” is taken in the unusual communalsense; the beliefs which individual speakers express by utterances are, strictly speaking, not these dia-gonals. What they do express can be correctly accounted for in the just mentioned doubling of Kaplan’sframework.
best of our knowledge: ”This is water”, and we might still be wrong, because the alleged
sample of water may differ in essential aspects from other samples; water has a hidden
nature. On the other hand, if we all say to the best of our knowledge: ”This is red”, then
that object is red. There seems to be no hidden nature to be found in red things which
would separate between genuine redness and fake redness.
However, this is not quite true. Though redness seems to have an overt nature, it
does not show it under any circumstances. One’s individual color judgment can be mis-
taken; and there is in principle also the possibility of collective error. The light may be
strange; there is a whole set of optical tricks and delusions; there is collective madness;
and so forth. Thus, the colors show their seemingly overt nature only under normal con-
ditions, and the point is that these normal conditions have a hidden nature. This is most
easily and clearly demonstrated, with a familiar type of argument, for the normal con-
There is not only daylight and twilight, but also twinlight. Twinlight looks as white
and bright as daylight, and under twinlight all the things familiar to us look the very same
color as under daylight. Thus, without modern physics we could not tell apart daylight and
twinlight, and perhaps even present physics does not yet help. Now imagine that in some
possible world there is a kind of object which we have not encountered so far; let us call
them modaleons. In daylight modaleons look deep blue; in twinlight they look glaring red.
In contrast to what Nida-Rümelin (Chapter 16 of this book) prefers from her point
of view, it would not be appropriate, I think, to say that modaleons change color when the
index world changes normal light. When talking counterfactually about changing light we
would not say, for instance, that sunflowers would be orange if a huge red filter were fixed
between the sun and the earth; rather we would say that they look orange under these
circumstances, though they still are yellow. Similarly, we would say that modaleons, which
are actually blue, would still be blue, but look red if the world were filled with twinlight.
Consider now different context worlds with different normal light; for all we know
the context world we live in may be filled with daylight or with twinlight. If the foregoing
is granted, then the modaleon case clearly shows the extension of color terms to vary with
the context world. Viewed from a context world filled with daylight, modaleons are blue,
whichever index world they inhabit; viewed from another context world filled with
twinlight, however, modaleons are not blue, but red. So, this example shows the hidden
nature at least of the normal lighting conditions and thus at the same time the context
dependence of the predicate λx(x is red).
This remote reason for the context dependence of color predicates of the type (A)
vanishes, if we turn to color predicates of the type (B); how things look to us at a given
moment no longer depends on such normal conditions. Thus, we might expect that terms
of type (B) are not context-dependent; this would also conform to the traditional view that
we cannot be mistaken about which color something looks to us at a given moment. But
Claim 2: Color predicates like (B) λxy(x appears red to y) are hidden indexicals.
The reason is basically that there are what I take to be clear cases falling under the
heading ‘inverted qualia’. For better explanation I have to introduce a very coarse piece of
current color perception theory. As is well known, the human retina contains a lot of cones,
each of which is equipped with one of three kinds of pigments. All three pigments are
sensitive to large parts of the visible spectrum, but in varying degrees. The maximal
sensitivity of the pigments lies, respectively, in the red, the green, and the blue segment of
the spectrum. So, the pigments are called R-, G-, and B-pigments; and accordingly, the
cones containing them are called R-, G-, and B-cones. A decisive link between the activity
of the cones triggered by the incoming light and the color sensation is now provided by
the so-called opponent process theory. According to this theory, the activity of the R- and
the G-cones is compared closely behind the retina. The more the activity of the R-cones
outweighs that of the G-cones, the more reddish is the color impression; and vice versa.
Moreover, the activity of the R- and the G-cones is summed up and compared with the one
of the B-cones. Again the more the sum outweighs the activity of the B-cones, the more
yellowish is the impression; and the more the activity of the B-cones preponderates, the
more bluish is the impression.15 It is important not to get confused here about the
classifications underlying the labels R, G, and B. The pigments so labeled are classified
according to their chemistry.16 By contrast, the opponent process theory offers a
functional criterion for classifying cones as R-, G-, and B-cones; they are so classified
One of the many explanatory achievements of the opponent process theory is that it
can explain dichromatism or red-green blindness. The explanation is simply that for some
reason both the R- and the G-cones contain the same pigments, so that their activity is
always the same and no impression tends to be reddish or greenish.18
The details are quite complicated, however, and empirical research is extremely difficult; cf., e.g.,
In fact, there occur not only the three normal forms, but also a number of chemical variations; cf.
Because of their symmetrical role, the issue of distinguishing R- and G-cones is quite subtle, how-
ever; cf. Nida-Rümelin (Chapter 16 of this book) for more detailed considerations.
Note that this explanation presupposes the independence of the classifications of pigments and cones
Now, Piantanida (1974) had a special hypothesis about dichromatism. Obviously,
red-green blindness may come in two forms; either the R-pigments are contained also in
the G-cones, or the G-pigments are contained also in the R-cones. Piantanida conjectured,
very roughly19, first that both forms are due to genetic defects, second that these defects
are located on different genes and are thus statistically independent, and third that there is
consequently a slight chance of suffering from both defects. For male persons this chance
is about 1.4 per thousand. Would such a male be color-blind? No; his discriminatory
powers are precisely as fine-grained as ours, only his reddish and greenish impressions
are reversed. Such persons are called pseudonormal. Obviously, it is very difficult, if not
impossible without violating bodily integrity to find out about pseudonormality, even for
the pseudonormals themselves. But perhaps you, dear reader, are one of those! It is not so
unlikely; for instance, about 58,000 of the 40 million male Germans would be
I do not know the scientific fate of Piantanida’s hypotheses, and I cannot assess
their scientific plausibility. But clearly, they make perfect sense, they are testable, and they
might well turn out to be true.20 The crucial point is how we should talk about
pseudonormals. I find it very clear that the right way to talk about them is just as I did,
namely that their reddish and greenish sensations are reversed; thus, red peppers look
green to them and green peppers look red to them. I would not know how to conclusively
refute those who refuse to talk that way, but it will become still clearer in the course of the
paper that this is indeed a meaningful way of talking.21 One may also sense an ambiguity
and think that it is equally appropriate to say that red peppers look red to pseudonormals,
that is, look as red things look to them. I shall discuss this alleged ambiguity in a moment;
but the primary sense of ”looks”, and the one I am presently referring to, is the one in
which red peppers look green to pseudonormals.
Now I am finally prepared to explain the context dependence of the term (B) λxy(x
looks or appears red to y). Take a situation in which someone with G-pigment in his R-
cones and R-pigment in his G-cones looks at a ripe tomato. Viewed from our actual
context world where most English-speaking people have R-pigment in their R-cones and
G-pigment in their G-cones, that person has a deviant color perception, and the situation
must be described as one in which the ripe tomato appears green to him. Viewed from a
context world, however, in which most English-speaking people have their pigments re-19
For details, see also Boynton (1979, 351-8).
Hilbert (1987, 92) seems to be the first to have mentioned pseudonormality in the philosophical
literature; but apparently only Nida-Rümelin (1993, chap. 4, and 1996) fully realized its philosophicalsignificance.
The point is more fully argued by Nida-Rümelin (1996).
versed22, that person is perfectly normal; and the situation must be described as one in
which the tomato appears red to him. Thus, to conclude, the truth value of ”that tomato
appears red to this person” as applied to one and the same situation varies with the con-
text–whence the context-dependence of appearance terms.
Is that meant to say that you may be mistaken when you, well-educated, fully at-
tentive, and absolutely sincere, as you are, say: ”This tomato looks red to me”? Yes,
precisely. Unbeknownst to you, you may be pseudonormal, and your utterance may thus
be false. The point of the argument is simply that the application of λxy(x appears red to
y) is relative to a standard of normal vision, that the context world sets this normality
standard, that the nature of this standard is unknown, and that no one knows for sure
whether he conforms to that standard or not.
This seems to make the doubtful presupposition that there is a standard of normal
vision. Is it not possible that Piantanida’s statistics are wrong and that, say, a third of the
population is pseudonormal? Surely; in fact, if one looks at perception experiments, one
sees a surprisingly large variation in human color perception. (Cf. Boynton 1979, chap.
10, and Hardin 1988.) But I do not need this presupposition, just as Putnam need not
presuppose that water, or jade, for that matter, is just one substance. (Cf. Putnam 1975,
239-41.) On the contrary, our essentiality convention for appearance terms responds flex-
For further explanation, I would like to relate this point to the familiar view due to
Chisholm (1957, chap. 4) that appearance terms have three different readings, a pheno-
menal, a comparative, and an epistemic reading. This is my
Claim 3: The phenomenal, the comparative, and the epistemic interpretation of λxy(x
appears red to y) are not three different readings; rather, they reflect the context
dependence of this term by being appropriate in three different kinds of con-
Let me briefly recall these three interpretations:
Clearly, this is a possible context world. Which kind of biochemical substance is in which kind of
so-and-so connected cones of most English-speaking people is a contingent matter about which we neednot have any knowledge.
According to the epistemic interpretation, ”x appears red to y” says as much as ” i n
the absence of counterevidence, y’s encounter with x tends to produce y’s belief that
According to the comparative interpretation, ”x appears red to y” means ”x looks to
y in the way red things usually look to y”.
For the phenomenal interpretation, finally, there is no such paraphrase; there ” x
appears red to y” holds only if y has a specific common type of qualitative ex-
We have seen (footnote 12) that according to our essentiality convention for
”water” the essential properties for being water depend on the actual properties of the
many ”water”-paradigms we have in the context world–whence the context dependence of
”water”. The very same is true of ”appearing red”, as these three interpretations reflect:
Imagine Case 1 which I take to be actually obtaining: In this case there are few
people with deviant perceptual capacities; there are few color-blinds and few or no pseu-
donormals. There may be variations; the sensitivity of the pigments may slightly differ in
different people; the neurons comparing the activities of the cones may not respond in a
completely uniform way; and so on. But on the whole most people have a roughly equal
functional and physiological arrangement of the visual apparatus including higher brain
regions. In that case, we would apply λy∃x(x appears red to y)24 only to those normal
people whose visual system is in a certain state; we could apply it also to some deviant
people, if their deviation is as simple as that of pseudonormals. But we would not further
extend the application. In that case, i.e. in such context worlds, the appropriate interpre-
tation of λxy(x appears red to y) is the phenomenal one in which it involves a particular
Now compare this with Case2. Its simplest version is that there are so many pseu-
donormal persons that they cannot be dismissed as deviant; there are just two normal
kinds of visual systems. In that case, each group can claim with equal right that ripe
tomatoes, for instance, look red to its members; it would have no point if the members of
either of the two groups insisted that tomatoes look red only to them. Thus, λxy(x appears
red to y) does not involve a certain phenomenal quality in this case. This is particularly
clear from the fact that in this version objects appearing red to one group produce the same
Or in Pitcher’s more careful words: ”y causally-receives, by means of using his eyes in the standard
visual way, the (perceptual) belief, or an inclination to have the (perceptual) belief, or a suppressedinclination to have a (perceptual) belief, that x is red”; cf. Pitcher (1971, 85-95).
This is to replace the awkward colloquial phrase ”is appeared red to” introduced by Chisholm (1957,
62) by a less awkward formal phrase.
phenomenal quality as objects appearing green to the other group. It is still clearer in cases
where there are many human visual systems which even the most advanced future science
is unable to match; then the phenomenal qualities experienced by our fellows would be
just as foreign to us as those of the bat. Still, color talk miraculously runs as smooth as it
does. So, these would be cases or contexts in which the comparative interpretation ofλxy(x appears red to y) is appropriate; λy∃x(x appears red to y) would then be applicableto all beings having qualitative experiences which somehow enable them to discriminate
and classify red things as we do, even though this ability would remain mysterious.25
There is the even less demanding Case 3, the absent qualia case. It seems perfectly
imaginable that some individuals behave in the very same way as we do without having any
phenomenal experience at all. Why should computers be able to pass the Turing test only
if they have built-in sensations? Think also of such things as blind-sight where people
with a specific brain damage behave toward objects similarly as normal people do but are
unable to report any conscious visual experience. (Cf., e.g., Weiskrantz 1980.) If this is
imaginable, it might turn out to hold in the context world. You are presumably quite sure
that you have phenomenal experiences. But perhaps you are one of the very few gifted
people; the normal case may be to have no visual experiences at all, but to talk as if one
had some. But we would still have our usual color talk. And we would still have beliefs; in
some mysterious way our beliefs are pushed this way and that way by our encounters with
the things in the world. This then is the way things appear to us. So, in this extreme case at
least, only the epistemic interpretation of λxy(x appears red to y) seems appropriate.
So, what is essential for λxy(x appears red to y) depends, according to our linguistic
essentiality convention, on how the context turns out to be; and the three interpretations
just mark three significantly different kinds of contexts. They are thus integrated into a
single character of λxy(x appears red to y).
It may be that I have overestimated human uniformity and that human vision is so varied as to rather
fall under Case 2; this is an empirical question (possibly undecidable due to vagueness). However, Straw-son (1989) argues, I understand, that Case 2 yields the appropriate description of the meaning of ”red” inany case. I do not agree. In an important argument (§6) he considers Monet and Renoir color vision(which is analogous to normal and pseudonormal vision) and asks whether the meaning of ”red” changeswhen English gets smoothly translated into the language of a population with Renoir vision (or when theshare of Renoir vision among English-speaking people slowly increases from 0 or 1 to 99 or 100 per-cent). His answer is: surely not; and the reason seems to be that there cannot be meaning changes whichnobody noticed. However, if meanings are explicated as characters there can be unnoticed meaningchanges, as is carefully explained by Haas-Spohn (in Section 4 of Chapter 14 of this book). Think againof ”water” (which is less confusing than ”red”) and of Putnam’s Twin Earth: It makes a difference whetherwe travel there before or after being able to distinguish between H20 and XYZ. If we travel there afterhaving this ability, XYZ never gets into the extension of English ”water”. But if we travel there before(and do this very often and develop a close interchange with Twin Earth), then the character and indeed theextension of English ”water” has changed; at the outset XYZ did not belong to it and later on it does. Strawson apparently does not observe this difference.
Why then did they appear to be three different readings and thus to uncover an
ambiguity? The reason, it seems to me, is that ”appear” and ”look” are conjoined not
only with ”red”, but with many other phrases as well. In fact, the usual claim associated
with these readings is that the scheme ”looking F ” (and not its instantiation ”looking
red”) has three different readings, depending on what is taken as F; and this claim is
usually accompanied by quite determinate opinions concerning which reading is
appropriate for which kind of F. My claim 3 interprets this determinateness as a (maybe
unreflected) certainty about the actual context world and the interpretation of ”looking F ”
For instance, it seems very likely that we live in a context world where ”appearing
red” carries the phenomenal interpretation. Again, circumstances seem to be such that a
comparative interpretation is most appropriate for phrases like ”appearing square” or
”looking like a capital A”, which are about simple forms possibly appearing in many
different ways. Finally, as things stand, the epistemic interpretation seems applicable not
only to perceiving beings without phenomenal experience, but also to us for phrases like
”appearing to be a car” where the appearance is phenomenally too complex and varied
and best reduced to the proximate epistemic effect.
However, for all these instantiations of ”looking or appearing F ” it seems possible
to imagine cases which show the same context-dependence as I have displayed it for
”appearing red”. Imagine, for instance, beings who have phenomenal experiences, but
who see only letters, maybe in Garamond. Thus, if a car is approaching them, they read
”car” written in Garamond in the relevant place of their visual field (strangely, these
beings are tuned to English); and one may refine the example by giving meaning to the
size and color of the letters in their visual field. For such beings a phenomenal interpreta-
tion of ”appearing to be a car” seems appropriate.26 Hence we find the three interpreta-
tions not only across the various instantiations of the scheme ”looking F ”, but indeed
within each locution of this type; and this, so I have argued, is better accounted for by
giving this locution one context-dependent meaning. Only if one neglects this context de-
pendence do there seem to be three different readings or meanings.
Let me summarize the point of claim 3 in a somewhat different way: There are two
extreme views to be found in the literature. Some think that subjects have certain types of
sense impressions, qualitative experiences, or whatever one may call them, that we can refer
to the subjects’ having them, maybe even in a direct or rigid way, and that we in fact do so
This example came to my mind when reading Cresswell (1980, 129-31), where he invents similarly
weird examples for arguing, contra Jackson, that there is no difference between ”looking red” and ”lookinglike a tomato”, i.e. that both may be equally given a phenomenal and a comparative reading. Thisargument further illustrates my present point.
with such expressions like λy∃x(x appears red to y) 27
expression of the opposite view is found in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations,
§293, where he ponders about how we could talk about the alleged beetles in our boxes
when everyone can look only into his or her own box and where he says:
Here it would be quite possible for everyone to have something different in his box. One mighteven imagine such a thing constantly changing. – But suppose the word ”beetle” had a use in thesepeople’s language? – If so, it would not be used as the name of a thing. The thing in the box hasno place in the language-game at all; not even as a something, for the box might even be empty. – No, one can ”divide through” by the thing in the box; it cancels out, whatever it is.
My claim 3 proposes a middle course agreeing, in a way, with both views. Witt-
genstein is right: Our communication with the very language and the very color express-
ions we have obviously works well, however the empirical facts turn out to be and even if
our boxes are empty; and a theory of meaning for this language has to do justice to this
fact, as my account tries to do.28 But under happy circumstances, we have the same kind of
beetles in our boxes, and then we do talk about our beetles. Surely, it is very likely that the
circumstances are happy; confirming this is not impossible, and with such findings as the
opponent process theory we are indeed beginning to confirm this.
I turn now to the relation between the two kinds of color predicates, i.e., between (A)
λx(x is red) and (B) λxy(x appears red to y). Again, we find two extreme views both ofwhich hold that the one predicate is definable by or reducible to the other. On the one
hand, those maintaining an objectivist account of colors insist that λx(x is red) denotes an
objective property, i.e. a primary quality of objects by themselves. (Cf., e.g., Jackson and
Pargetter 1987.) They may add that λxy(x appears red to y) should be explained by how
subjects respond to objects’ being red; the comparative and the epistemic interpretation ofλxy(x appears red to y) precisely are attempts to give that explanation. But since thephenomenal interpretation turned out to be appropriate at least for some contexts, e.g.,
those where vision is realized in most humans in a relatively uniform way, this additional
claim does not seem defensible. On the other hand, those defending a subjectivist account
of colors say that the colors of objects are secondary qualities which can only be explained
by how the objects appear to us; they would thus cite statement
x is red if and only if x would appear red to most English-speaking people under
Cf., e.g., Nida-Rümelin (Chapter 16 in this book). As she emphasizes in Section 2.1, this does not
necessarily require to posit objects like impressions, sensations, etc.
This is not to say, however, that my application of Kaplan’s framework to color talk would have a
specifically Wittgensteinian character.
as a definition or an analysis of being red.29 In order to assess this, we have to inquire into
the modal status of (1).30 This is the content of my
Claim 4: (1) is a priori in English31; but it is analytic only in one reading and not analytic
We find out about the apriority of (1) by evaluating it in each context (and its asso-
ciated index). There (1) seems to be true; I cannot imagine any context world in which the
two sides of the equivalence in (1) would differ in truth value. In any case, (1) is true in all
three kinds of contexts for which the three interpretations of λxy(x appears red to y) are,
respectively, appropriate. This just reflects the point noted earlier that the colors of things
have an overt nature given normal conditions; in no context can an object which appeared
red to most of us under normal conditions turn out not to be red, and vice versa.32
We find out about the analyticity of (1) by evaluating it in each context and each
index; (1) is analytic if and only if it is true in all of them. Consider, for instance, the actual
context with a ripe tomato before us and transfer the tomato just as it is into some
counterfactual index world i. Thus, this tomato is as red in i as it is here. Now let us
assume that most English speaking people in i are pseudonormal, that is, have R-pigment
in their G-cones and G-pigment in their R-cones; this is definitely a possible counter-
factual supposition. Since I take it that the actual context is one in which pseudonormals
are deviant people with red-green-inverted sensations, we would then have to say that most
English-speaking people have red-green-inverted sensations in i. So in particular, it is true
in the index world i that the red tomato appears green to most English-speaking people.
This amounts to a counterexample to the analyticity of (1).
This is explicitly done, for instance, by McGinn (1983, 5-14) –with the exception that he would not
restrict (1) to English-speaking people. This minor difference is cleared up in footnote 31.
In Spohn (1997) I have again used the Kaplanian framework for a related inquiry into the modal status
of reduction sentences for dispositional predicates in general and also into the epistemology and ontologyof normal conditions. This inquiry may further illuminate the following discussion.
This explains my restriction of (1) to English-speaking people; the primary standard for how ”being
red” works in English is the English-speaking community. The situation changes as soon as there areestablished translations between English and other languages; then the people speaking these otherlanguages become equally important. Cf. Haas-Spohn (1995, § III).
Since I am talking about apriority in English. I am not claiming that (1) is a priori for any subject.
This also entails that it would be inappropriate to object that a thing could be red in a context where thereare no English-speaking people for it to appear red. This is so because the existence of the English-speak-ing community is a priori in English, similarly as my existence is a priori for me. But, of course, theexistence of the English-speaking community is not analytic in English. This as well as the mere aprior-ity of one reading of (1) are examples showing that apriority in English is an independent notion reducibleneither to analyticity nor to subjective apriority. And this in turn shows that such communal epistemicnotions are needed; at least there is some work for them to do.
However, my claim 4 seems to state an ambiguity in (1). Where is it? I have just
understood ”most English-speaking people” in an attributive way by evaluating it at the
index world i itself. But we can take this phrase also in a referential way as referring to
most English people not in the index, but in the context world c. The same kind of
ambiguity can be found in the phrase ”under normal conditions”; it can refer to
conditions counting as normal in i or counting as normal in c.33 To make this referential
reading more explicit, statement (1) thus read says in each context c:
x is red in the index world i if and only if x would appear red in i to most English-
speaking people from c under conditions normal in c.
The counterexample above does not apply to this reading. Indeed, I cannot think of any
counterfactual index world i for which this reading would not be true. If this is correct,
There would be no point in arguing which reading is more natural. The important
thing to note, I think, is that (1) is a priori in any case and that it is analytic only in the
referential reading (of the relevant phrases), but not in its attributive reading.
Does this result support the subjectivist in any way? No. A preliminary point to note
is that an analytic equivalence like (1) in its referential reading need not give a definition or
analysis; as an analytic truth it just states a certain meaning relation. But since it is not so
clear, anyway, what an analysis or a definition (of an already meaningful term of natural
language) is beyond an analytic equivalence, we had better concentrate on the subjectivist’s
claim that colors are secondary qualities, or that predicates of type (A) are dispositional or,
more abstractly, relational, i.e., relative to perceiving subjects:
What the subjectivist would need is the necessary or, as McGinn (1983, 14) puts it,
intrinsic dispositionality or relationality of type (A) terms. This, however, cannot be in-
ferred from my claim 4. λx(x is red) would be necessarily relational in a given context if
and only if, viewed from that context, an object could be red in an index world only if it
would stand in a certain (maybe only dispositional or counterfactual) relation to other
objects in that index world. (1) seems to assert such a thing; but it does so only in its
attributive reading which I observed to hold only a priori, i.e., not to be projectible from the
The distinction between an attributive and a referential use of denoting phrases was originally in-
troduced by Donnellan (1966), however in an apparently different way. By using it as just explained I referto its standard interpretation within the Kaplanian framework which is to be found in Stalnaker (1970) andKaplan (1978).
Maund (1986, 173-6) makes a similar point by distinguishing a purely comparative and a referential
use of ”looks” and arguing that something like (1) is analytic in the first, but synthetic in the second use;however, he does not represent his distinction within the Kaplanian framework.
context to all indices. Nor does the referential reading help, despite its analyticity, since it
asserts only a certain relation between objects’ being red in an index world and the people
in the context world. Compare this with λx(x is a mother), the standard example of a
necessarily relational predicate. Here, viewed from any context world, someone is a mother
in an index world if and only if someone else exists or has existed in that index world who
is her child. The analogous assertion for ”being red” is simply not licensed by the modal
What is licensed by the apriority of the attributive reading of (1) is the conclusion
that λx(x is red) is a priori relational. But this is no peculiarity of color terms; according to
Haas-Spohn (Chapter 14 of this book), ”water” and other natural kind terms, in fact all
hiddenly indexical predicates and thus many predicates which unquestionably denote pri-
mary qualities are a priori relational.36
But even if the necessary relationality of λx(x is red) cannot be demonstrated, it may
actually hold in a given context. Maybe; I was, however, unable to imagine such a context.
I shall return to this issue with my claim 6 when I speculate about our actual context
So far, I have considered all possible contexts for our two sample predicates (A) and
(B). I have, implicitly and explicitly, discussed their diagonal and how to project their
extension from contexts to other indices; in this sense I have carried out an episte-
mological and semantical investigation. After all this it is not so difficult to give a summa-
rizing definition of the character of these predicates.37 In the rest of the paper, however, I35
Jackson and Pargetter (1987, 130 f) argue for the same point. They call (1) the dispositional truism
and argue that the truism does not justify one in identifying colors with the disposition to look colored;rather, colors should be identified with the categorical base of this disposition. I agree, if one takes thedifference between a disposition and its categorical base to be only an epistemological one: The intensionof a dispositional predicate and the intension of the predicate describing the categorical base are thesame–both predicates denote the same property; but their diagonals and a fortiori their characters aredifferent. With this account of the difference between dispositions and their bases, my argument is thesame as theirs. However, Prior, Pargetter, and Jackson (1982, 253 ff) give an ontological account of thedifference. So, there remains a disagreement. I discuss this disagreement more fully in Spohn (1997b).
Compare also the discussion about the notion of response dependence and its rigid and its nonrigid
interpretation which addresses the very same issues; cf., e.g., Vallentyne (1996). I think this notion nicelyfits into the Kaplanian framework; its rigid and its nonrigid interpretation, in particular, correspond to thereferential and the attributive use as explained above.
Applying the general scheme of Haas-Spohn (1995, 151) to our sample predicates we get: x is red in
the context c and the index i iff x shares in i all the properties which, according to the English essentialityconvention for ”being red”, are essential in c for the redness of the objects to which ”being red” is ty-pically applied in c by the English speaking community; and x appears red to y in the context c and theindex i iff x and y possess in i all the properties and relations which, according to the English essentialityconvention for ”appearing red”, are essential in c for the relation of appearing red between any two objectsto which ”appearing red” is typically applied in c by the English-speaking community. This abstractexplanation is neither circular nor badly metalinguistic (cf. Haas-Spohn, Chapter 14 of this book and1995, §§ 3.4, 3.5). But it is less illuminating than the substantiation of its key terms for the case athand; and I am here rather concerned with the latter.
shall engage in a metaphysical speculation concerning the intension of these predicates at
x appears red to y if and only if x (appropriately) causes y to be in a neural state of
Claim 5: For some (possibly disjunctive) kind N of neural states, statement (2) is ne-
cessarily true in the actual context.
The parenthetical ”appropriately” in statement (2) is to exclude deviant ways of causation
which do not count as an object’s appearing to a subject; but I am not concerned with
spelling out what is to count as appropriate here (cf., e.g., Lewis 1980). Of course, claim 5
similarly holds for other color appearance terms; thus it says in effect that color
appearance terms are strongly supervenient on neural state terms, or, what comes to the
same, that the property of having-a-so-and-so-colored-sensation is type-type identical with
the property of being in a certain (possibly wildly disjunctive) neural state.38
Claim 5 consists of two parts. The first is a factual hypothesis, namely that (2) is
actually true for some N, or rather that in most of our actual paradigm cases for some
object’s appearing red to some subject we find in that subject an activation of a certain
neural structure or a realization of a certain, possibly very complex neural state. As far as I
know, brain research has not come up so far with results disconfirming this hypothesis;
but perhaps I am underestimating the complexity and diversity of neurological findings.
Or–perhaps I am again underestimating present expertise–we do not seem to have any
good theory what that kind N of neural state might be. But this only shows how poor our
knowledge is; it does not show the senselessness or illegitimacy of that hypothesis.
The second part of claim 5 is a claim about our essentiality convention for λxy(x
appears red to y), namely, the claim that, given the factual hypothesis that we find a neural
state type N uniformly realized in most of our paradigm cases of λy∃x(x appears red to y),
this state type N provides the essence of λy∃x(x appears red to y); that is, we would
correctly apply λy∃x(x appears red to y) only to factual and counterfactual cases in which
this state type is realized. So, this is rather a linguistic claim about our counterfactual talk.
It is to be defended mainly against two doubts.
Here I identify the property expressed by a predicate with its intension, so that necessary universal
equivalence of two predicates is necessary and sufficient for the identity of the properties expressed. Forthe equivalence of strong supervenience and type-type identity cf., e.g., Kim (1984, § IV).
One doubt is whether, given the factual hypothesis, the essence of λxy(x appears red
to y) is really to be conceived so narrowly as to conform to no wider than the phenomenal
interpretation. I have briefly discussed this already in Case 1 following the three
interpretations (E), (C), and (P). One possible ground for abandoning this doubt is how I
said we would talk about pseudonormals; when we say that red peppers would appear
green to them, we precisely assume the narrow essence. Another possible ground is that
we say that, strictly speaking, nothing appears green or red to red-green-blind people even
if they should have other clues for correctly guessing the colors. Still another ground is
that we refuse, as I think we should, to carry over human color talk to, say, bees upon
finding that bees carve up the space of electromagnetic wave mixtures in quite a different
and incomparable way than we do. So this doubt seems unfounded.
The other doubt is whether claim 5 provides a correct understanding of the pheno-
menal interpretation. One may rather think that it is the phenomenal quality itself which is
essential for red appearances, i.e., that, necessarily, x appears red to y if and only if x
(appropriately) causes y to have a red-sensation39; it would thus be a matter of contingency
which kind of brain states are correlated with red-sensations.40 I have two reasons for
First, if the correlation of neural states with red-sensations is contingent in any case,
then conceiving λxy(x appears red to y) as context-dependent and describing this
dependence as I did in claim 3 loses its plausibility; it goes together more naturally with
the view (endorsed by Nida-Rümelin in this volume) that everyone, when claiming that
something appears red to him, refers to the kind of phenomenal quality which he is just
experiencing and the awareness of which leaves no room for error and thus for hidden
indexicality. The consequence of conceiving λxy(x appears red to y) as involving a fixed
kind of phenomenal quality in all contexts and indices is, however, that the few pseudo-
normals, if they exist, always refer to another quality than normal people do, hence useλxy(x appears red to y) with a different meaning (character) and speak, in a sense, a dif-ferent language. The more varied version of Case 2 mentioned after the three interpreta-
tions (E), (C), and (P) comes out even worse according to this view; there would be a
Babylonian confusion where λxy(x appears red to y) would have many different meanings
and people would talk many different languages. 39
Here, the unusual locution of having a red-sensation is defined as denoting the property which is
caused to apply to a subject by an object iff that object appears red to it; in other words, it denotes theintrinsic, nonrelational property which a subject has whenever the relational property λy∃x(x appears redto y) applies to it (and which a subject may also have, as it turns out, without external cause).
Certainly, this better catches the intentions of the adherents of the phenomenal interpretation. Kripke
(1972) seems to think so with respect to pains (though not necessarily with respect to colors) (cf. pp. 334ff). Clearly, Nida-Rümelin (Chapter 16 of this book) also favors this view.
This seems unwarranted to me. I do not know whether Case 1, 2, or 3 obtains
(though I have already expressed my prejudice); but in any case I see no reason to assume
such a possible multiplicity of languages. For instance, if Case 1 should turn out to hold
and if some pseudonormals should be identified, my prediction would be that these
pseudonormals would not insist to continue speaking as before; they would rather correct
themselves and agree to such things as that, strictly speaking, red tomatoes look green to
them; i.e., they would submit to common usage. Or, if, to our great surprise, Case 2 should
turn out to obtain, my prediction is that linguistic practice would not change a bit; after this
discovery, all of us would talk of things appearing red to us as we did before. This does
not look like a discovery of many languages where there seemed to be only one.41
Maybe, however, the disagreement is not about the context dependence of λxy(x
appears red to y), but only about the essential properties of λxy(x appears red to y) in the
presumably obtaining Case 1. Then I have a second reason for sticking to claim 5, namely
Internal realism, as I understand it, asserts that truth is believable or discoverable;
given a correct understanding of the ”-able”–this is all-important–I believe that internal
realism provides the defensible core of verificationism.42 Now, it seems to me that internal
realism may be strengthened to assert that essences are believable or discoverable. I have
no clear argument for this claim43; but if so much is granted, my argument can proceed:
Let us imagine that we have investigated vision in human as well as in other sensing
beings as completely as possible; for instance, we have constructed fabulous devices with
which we can scan brain states in real time. After endless ingenious theorizing and
ingenious experimenting we have come up with our final theory about vision, how visual
input is processed, how consciousness comes into play, how all this leads to linguistic and
other behavioral output, etc.44 According to internal realism this final theory which cannot
be shattered or improved by any further findings is true. The final theory will contain
If these predictions would turn out false, however, this might well be reason for me to revise my po-
I interpret the ”-able” in the following way: the set of a posteriori truths and our inductive standards
(taken in a broad sense) must be such that each truth is inductively supported by other truths (condi-tionally on arbitrarily many truths) and can thus be believed on true grounds. In Spohn (1991) I formallyexplicated this idea and proved it to be equivalent, in a way, with the universal feasibility of causal expla-nation.
A major difficulty is here to adapt all the notions involved in the explication of internal realism to the
more sophisticated Kaplanian framework. In Spohn (1991) I have not dealt with this difficulty simplybecause I was not yet aware of it.
Maybe we even have constructed a transmitter cap and a receiver cap directly connecting two brains,
and our final theory says that the human under the receiving cap should experience similar sensations tothe being under the transmitting cap.
many equivalences of the form (2) all of which are true; an object will appear red to a
perceiver if and only if a many-membered chain of events is realized, each of which is a
necessary and sufficient cause of the later ones. Among all these equivalences there will be
one referring to a special neural state type N* with the further characteristic that, given a
subject x is in state N*, there is no further or overriding reason whatsoever for or against
x’s having a red-sensation and that, given a subject x is not in state N*, there is no further
or overriding reason whatsoever for or against x’s not having a red-sensation; that is, any
reason for a divergence between being in state N* and having a red-sensation would at the
same time disconfirm the final theory. But then it would be strange to insist that the
essence of having a red-sensation does not consist in the neural state type N*, but in
something else. In any case, no reasons whatsoever could be adduced in favor of this, not
even by the perceiver herself; and then it is simply false according to the strengthened
x is red if and only if the reflectance spectrum of the surface of x is of the kind RClaim 6: For some (possibly disjunctive) kind R of reflectance spectrum, statement (3) is
necessarily true in the actual context.
In order to see this, we do not have to do much more than putting together claim 5 and the
analytic reading (4) of assertion (1). If we do this we get:
In the actual context it is necessarily true for some neural state type N that x is red if
and only if x would cause most of the actual English-speaking people under actual
normal conditions to be in state N.
Now, there are certainly many ways for people to get into a neural state of kind N and for a
given object to bring this about; the actual causal story seems to be a matter of contingent
Let me clarify the hypothetical and the positive content of the argument: In any case, I think, the
final theory will come up with some equivalence of the form ”x has a red-sensation iff x is P” with thecharacteristic just described. My positive claim is then that, according to strengthened internal realism,this P is the essence of having a red-sensation; and my hypothetical claim is that this P will actually turnout to be of the form ”being in neural state of type N*”. But the latter seems at least plausible. In anycase, if we tend not to leave it open, but to positively assert on the basis of the opponent process theorythat green peppers look red and red peppers look green to pseudonormals and to stick to this until receiv-ing counterevidence, we are on the track of searching for, and being prepared to accept, ever more sophi-sticated neural conditions for having red-sensations–a track which will eventually lead us to the type N*required for claim 5 to be true.
physics and of contingent neurobiology. So how do we get from the necessary truth in (5)
to the necessary truth of (3)? This is achieved by the reference to normal conditions.
Recall my speculation about twinlight and the modaleons. Of course, an index world may
be filled with twinlight, and because physics is very different there, modaleons there
produce state type N in us; that is, they appear red to us. But as I have already argued after
claim 1, modaleons, when viewed from the actual context, would not count as red in that
index world, but as blue, because under normal conditions such as daylight they would
appear blue to us. Similar considerations apply to the normal conditions within the
subjects, like not being mad or intoxicated and so on. Thus it is the function of the
reference to normal conditions to keep the kind of causal process between visible objects
and the observers as it normally is in the actual context world fixed throughout all possible
index worlds. This enables us to locate, so to speak, the color of an object with necessity in
the object itself; we do not have to settle for merely contingent correlations between the
physical properties of an object and its color. And for all we know, it is the reflectance
spectrum of the object’s surface which is the relevant physical property. Of course, the
class R of reflectance spectra characterizing redness forms an extremely wild and certainly
quite vague region in the space of possible reflectance spectra. This is so because the class
R is specified only in relation to the equally vague neural state type N and thus to a very
According to claim 6, the nature of being red is hidden and unknown. Did it not
seem to be overt? Yes, it seemed so. But then we observed with claim 1 that already the
normal conditions have a hidden nature. With claim 2 we realized that the nature of ap-
pearing red is even more profoundly hidden. And this entails via the analyticity of (4) that
the nature of being red is equally profoundly hidden. The appearance of overtness could
be confirmed only under the variant of the phenomenal reading of λxy(x appears red to y)
which I have criticized under claim 5.
According to claim 6, moreover, colors are not dispositional properties or, more
specifically, secondary qualities of objects, contrary to a familiar view. What claim 6 does,
in effect, is simply to identify redness, i.e., the disposition of appearing red with its
categorical base. My general presumption is here that many, though probably not all
dispositions are such that having the disposition is necessarily, though certainly not ana-
In having this metaphysical position concerning colors I thus join what Hilbert (1987) calls
anthropocentric realism. My only disagreement is that I would insist that metamers have the same color,because metamers look to have the same color under normal conditions (bright daylight etc.) and becausethe real color of an object shows itself only under normal conditions. If a color is thus constituted by theclass of its metamers, the class R in assertion (3) is, for all we know, bound to be a wild one. To say, asHilbert (1987, 83 f) does, that only isomers have the same color would mean, I think, to revise ordinarycolor talk. Whether the revision would be a reasonable one is another question.
lytically equivalent with realizing the categorical base of the disposition. This looks im-
plausible only if one confuses ontology and epistemology. One may say that being red is
a dispositional concept, since it is a priori according to claim 4 that red things have the
disposition to look red; and it is this disposition which determines for each context which
property being red is. But this is an epistemological point which does not entail the onto-
logical point that this property itself is dispositional.47 The epistemological point is also
reflected in the fact that in order to find out about, and succinctly describe, the class R of
reflectance spectra we have to find out about, and to refer to, the human visual system and
possibly to the class N of neural states. But again, this does not entail that the property of
having a reflectance spectrum belonging to the class R would be relational in any way.
To be sure, what claims 5 and 6 say about the actual context world may be far from
the truth, and then the a posteriori necessities may be very different; no one can claim
certainty about this. But there is at least hope that the context world we live in is so nice as
to allow us to stick to the claims 5 and 6 and thus to be metaphysically conservative and
parsimonious, even though the epistemological picture I have drawn is much richer.
Almog, J. 1981. Dthis and Dthat: Indexicality Goes beyond That. Philosophical Studies 39: 347-81.
––– 1984. Would You Believe That? Synthese 58: 1-37.
Boynton, R. M. 1979. Human Color Vision. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Burge, T. 1979. Individualism and the Mental. In P. A. French, T. E. Uehling jr., and H. K. Wettstein,
eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. IV: Metaphysics. Minneapolis: University ofMinnesota Press, pp. 73-121.
Chisholm, R. M. 1957. Perceiving: A Philosophical Study. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
Cresswell, M. J. 1980. Jackson on Perception. Theoria 46: 123-47.
Donnellan, K. 1966. Reference and Definite Descriptions. Philosophical Review 75: 281-304.
Haas-Spohn, U. 1995. Versteckte Indexikalität und subjektive Bedeutung. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.
Hardin, C. L. 1988. Color for Philosophers. Indianapolis: Hackett.
Hilbert, D. R. 1987. Color and Color Perception. A Study in Anthropocentric Realism. CSLI Lecture
Jackson, F., and R. Pargetter 1987. An Objectivist’s Guide to Subjectivism about Color. Revue Inter-nationale de Philosophie 41: 127-41.
Kaplan, D. 1977. Demonstratives. An Essay on the Semantics, Logic, Metaphysics, and Epistemology of
Demonstratives and Other Indexicals. In J. Almog, J. Perry, and H. Wettstein, eds., Themes fromKaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989, pp. 481-563.
––– 1978. Dthat. In P. Cole, ed., Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 9: Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press,
Cf. my remarks about necessary and a priori relationality in my discussion of claim 4.
Kim, J. 1984. Concepts of Supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45: 153-76.
Kripke, S. A. 1972. Naming and Necessity. In D. Davidson and G. Harman, eds., Semantics of NaturalLanguage. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 253-355 and 763-9.
––– 1979. A Puzzle about Belief. In A. Margalit, ed., Meaning and Use. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 239-83.
Lewis, D. 1980. Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58:
––– 1983. Philosophical Papers, Vol. I. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Maund, J. B. 1986. The Phenomenal and Other Uses of ”Looks”. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64:
Nida-Rümelin, M. 1993. Farben und phänomenales Wissen. Vienna: VWGÖ.
––– 1996. Pseudonormal Vision: An Actual Case of Qualia Inversion? Philosophical Studies 82: 145-57.
Piantanida, T. P. 1974. A Replacement Model of X-linked Recessive Colour Vision Defects. Annals of
Prior, E. W., R. Pargetter, and F. Jackson 1982. Three Theses about Dispositions. American Philoso-
Putnam, H. 1975. The Meaning of ”Meaning.” In H. Putnam, Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2: Mind, Lan-guage and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215-71.
Spohn, W. 1991. A Reason for Explanation: Explanations Provide Stable Reasons. In W. Spohn, B.
C. van Fraassen, and B. Skyrms, eds., Existence and Explanation. Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 165-96.
––– 1997a. Über die Gegenstände des Glaubens. In G. Meggle, ed., Proceedings of Analyomen 2, Berlin:
––– 1997b. Begründungen a priori - oder: ein frischer Blick auf Dispositionsprädikate. In W. Lenzen, ed.,
Das weite Spektrum der Analytischen Philosophie, Berlin: de Gruyter, 1997, pp. 323-45.
Stalnaker, R. C. 1970. Pragmatics. Synthese 22: 272-89.
––– 1978. Assertion. In P. Cole, ed., Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 9: Pragmatics. New York: Academic
––– 1987. Semantics for Belief. Philosophical Topics 15: 177-90.
Strawson, G. 1989, Red and ”Red.” Synthese 78: 193-232.
Vallentyne, P. 1996. Response-Dependence, Rigidification, and Objectivity. Erkenntnis 44: 101-12.
Weiskrantz, L. 1980. Varieties of Residual Experience. Quartely Journal of Experimental Psychology 32:
Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Transl. G. E. M. Anscombe, Oxford: Basil Black-
coordination and/or cause weakness, poor difficulty with walking, which is also cal ed balance, numbness, or spasticity (abnormal ambulation. The term “gait” refers more increase in muscle tone). Visual or cognitive specifically to the manner or pattern of problems can also interfere with walking. walking (for example “unsteady gait”). studies suggest that half the people with som
Development and Implementation of Bridge Management System in Aomori Prefectural Government Abstract Aomori Prefecture is located at the north end of Main Island of Japan, surrounded by sea on three sides and known as one of the heavy snow area in Japan. In the western region facing to Nippon Sea, severe salt damage has been observed on the bridges on the coastal roads due to the sa