Stan van Hooft Deakin University, Melbourne
This article reviews a number of recent books and practices that address a renewed
interest in the role that philosophy might play in the living of a rich and fulfilling life.
The review looks at books addressed to the general public as well as books which
discuss such classical and Hellenistic philosophers as took their task to be helping
people achieve happiness in life. It then turns to some newly emerging philosophical
practices such as philosophical counselling in order to explore whether philosophy
can still be a source of consolation or guidance in contemporary life.
Alain de Botton, The Consolations of Philosophy, Harmondsworth, Penguin Books,
Pierre Hadot, Philosophy as a way of life, (Edited and with an introduction by Arnold
Lou Marinoff, Plato not Prozac! Applying Eternal Wisdom to Everyday Problems,
Shlomit C. Schuster, Philosophy Practice: An Alternative to Counseling and Psychotherapy, Westport CT, Praeger, 1999.
Peter B. Raabe: Philosophical Counseling: Theory and Practice, Westport CT,
Introduction
There is a renewed interest these days in philosophy as a practice outside of the
academy and as an interest for non-professional philosophers. The focus of this
interest is the link between philosophy and the problems of daily life which, it is said,
are not addressed by a great deal of academic philosophy. A possible exception to this
claim is Michel Foucault’s recent work on the ‘care of the self’ which he sees as the
fundamental concern of classical ethics. But even this work is a part of his
genealogical/historical project exploring the emergence of the modern subject, rather
than an attempt to show how philosophy might help us live a richer and more
fulfilling life. This lecture reviews a number of recent books and practices that
address the latter interest and suggests that some themes of considerable philosophical
profundity lie at its base: themes about what constitutes a well-lived life, what is the
nature of the self, whether the self can even be known, and whether the practice of
philosophical inquiry and philosophical dialogue can, in themselves, help us to live
better lives. If, in the classical period, philosophy played a role similar to modern
psychotherapy, can it recover such a role today? Can it help us care for ourselves?
Popular Books
A great deal of public interest in philosophy has been stimulated by Alain de Botton’s
best selling book, The Consolations of Philosophy and the television series based on
it, Philosophy – a Guide to Happiness. The book comprises six chapters in each of
which a particular philosopher is invoked in order to provide insight and
encouragement in relation to problems which threaten happiness in human life. So
there is a chapter on how Socrates might help us with deal with unpopularity, how
Epicurus might have dealt with not having enough money, how Seneca might help us
face frustration, how Montaigne faced feelings of inadequacy, how a broken heart
might be relieved by thinking about Schopenhauer’s views on romantic love, and how
Nietzsche’s philosophy can help us cope with (but not overcome) difficulties.
The book is written for a popular lay audience and enhances its easy prose with
illustrations and diagrams. It tells the stories of the six philosophers’ lives as well as
explicating relevant themes from their philosophies in a way that is both engaging and
stimulating. Some professional philosophers who have reviewed the book have
complained that the explications of the philosophers’ thoughts are superficial, but
such a charge needs to be evaluated in the light of the author’s aims. Although there is
no preface which explains those aims, the dust jacket promises us ‘an indispensable
compendium of advice on how to deal with some of our most familiar woes’. It also
promises ‘a dazzling introduction to the history and uses of philosophy’. The latter the
book clearly is not. If the book were a history of philosophy, or even of the six
philosophers discussed, then we would expect a much more thorough treatment of the
ideas of these philosophers. In the case of Socrates we would expect a discussion of
such issues as the grounding of virtue in knowledge. We would expect to see the
practical advice of Epicurus and of Seneca grounded in their metaphysics of a natural
world ruled by chance and by reason respectively, and we would be told how
Montaigne’s views grow out of those of Epicurus and of Seneca. We would be shown
how Schopenhauer draws on the tradition of Plato and of how radically Nietzsche
rejected this tradition. But none of this is to de Botton’s purpose. For him, the issue is
simply what we can learn from these thinkers in order to help us face the difficulties
Socrates helps us face our own unpopularity because he allowed himself to become
unpopular in his community by asking troublesome questions. De Botton explains
why he did this and sets out the logical structure of his questioning, thereby giving us
some hints as to what it is to do philosophy. He also urges us to follow Socrates’
example in following only the dictates of reason rather than popular opinions. But the
main point which is meant to inspire us is that it was because of the courage of his
convictions that Socrates was unpopular and put to death. We should take comfort
from this and be inspired by it. Of course, it might be argued that unpopular people
should take a good hard look at themselves and ask themselves why they are
unpopular. The fault may lie with them. But this aside, there is no doubt that the story
that de Botton tells is an edifying one.
The problem is that it is the story that is edifying rather than the philosophy. We are
told what Socrates did in questioning his fellow Athenians. We are told about his trial
and his acceptance of death. But we are not told about Socrates’ philosophy apart
from a few illustrations of his questioning taken from Plato’s published dialogues. (Of
course it is difficult, if not impossible, to extricate Socrates’ thought from Plato’s, but
we are left to wonder whether there was any content of belief that Socrates was
prepared to die for, or whether it was just his practice of rational questioning which
was the object of his martyrdom.) The reader of the book is not given any reason to
take courage in the face of being unpopular. He is given an exemplar. The reader does
not have to do any philosophy in order to be comforted by Socrates. He or she needs
And so it is with the other five philosophers in the book. While we are given brief and
somewhat superficial descriptions of the content of their ideas, it is the story of their
lives and deaths that do the rhetorical work of giving comfort. So we are given
impressive glimpses of Epicurus’ communal and frugal life. We are appalled at
Seneca’s courageous obedience to Nero’s command that he kill himself. We are
relieved at the ordinariness of Montaigne’s life as a city official, petty nobleman, and
traveller. Schopenhauer was so unlikeable that one could not expect any but the most
pessimistic and deflationary conception of romantic love from him. And Nietzsche’s
views are grounded, not in the radically monistic metaphysics of the will-to-power,
but in his habit of taking walks in the mountains despite extreme physical ailments.
De Botton’s eloquent writing style makes these philosophers come alive for us on the
page. But if we are moved to receive consolation from them, it stems from their lives
rather than their ideas. The book should have been entitled The Consolations of Philosophers rather than The Consolations of Philosophy. There is very little
encouragement in the book for readers to begin to do philosophy for themselves. Very
few arguments are offered or critiqued. If there is consolation to be had from doing
philosophy or thinking philosophically, then this book does not teach us how to do
In the chapter on Epicurus, for example, we are warned against being seduced by
consumerist advertising and to value friends and rational thought. These nostrums are
easy to accept, but also easy to ignore. By what process can they be made influential
in one’s life? It is one thing to give them intellectual assent, it is another to be
motivated by them to change one’s life. How do we overcome the psychological need
for false consolations? Is it just ignorance (as in de Botton’s example of trepanning as
a benighted medical procedure) that needs to be overcome or are there deeper and
unconscious drives that move us? It would seem that de Botton’s strategy is that of the
classical homily or the modern motivational speaker: present an impressive life as an
inspiration to others. But if it is philosophy which is to be a fount of consolation or a
motivation for changing our lives for the better, then it should be the agent’s own
rational thought which effects the change. Does thinking philosophically, whether
‘philosophically’ is defined in relation to form or to content, have the power to change
The trouble seems to lie, as de Botton’s chapter on Seneca begins to make clear, in an
ancient philosophical anthropology. On this view, reason is a faculty or ‘part of the
soul’ whose role it is to control the passions. The ancients were at one in teaching the
art of rational control as the means for living one’s life well. The emotions were seen
as disruptive forces welling up from the lower parts of one’s being: namely, the body,
while reason, through which we participated in the life of the gods, had the task of
taking control. The Stoics famously urged us to achieve such control by extirpating
the passions. Plato’s theory was more complex but helped establish the bifurcation.
Can we still accept this view of human beings in today’s post-Freudian world? If
reason is the slave of the passions as Hume argued, and if the passions are as complex
and self-deceptive as Freud argued, why should we be confident that rational thought
will have any eudaimonistic influence on our lives? Perhaps it is because de Botton
has no answers to these questions that he appeals to the edifying biographies of his
philosophers rather than to their arguments.
Nietzsche is presented as standing in the tradition of Socrates. Yet it was he who has
done most to question the classical conception of reason and its predominance in
philosophy. With his wholly new conception of ‘psychology’ as a basis for
understanding ideas, de Botton could have opened up urgent questions about the role
that philosophy can play in the pursuit of a well-lived life. Instead we get little more
than homilies and nostrums about bearing up under stress. My complaint here is not
that de Botton has missed much that is important and valuable in Nietzsche. It is that
he has not shown us how philosophy has become, for this thinker, a wholly new and
different source of consolation in life: not as the rule of reason over the passions, but
as the acknowledgement of what we are deeply within ourselves and the
If de Botton’s book and his television series awaken an interest in philosophy in the
lay person, then he will have made a valuable contribution to contemporary life. There
will be several forms that such an interest might take.
Studies of the Ancients
One approach for a person inspired by de Botton to see how philosophy might help
them live life more satisfactorily will be a study of the very philosophers that de
Botton himself discusses. While there are many studies available that readers might
pursue, there are a few published in recent years which focus on the relevance of these
and other philosophers to the questions that de Botton raises: namely, how might
philosophy help us live our lives more fully so as to attain happiness? Let us explore
In his inaugural lecture at his accession to the Chair of the History of Hellenistic and
Roman Thought at the Collège de France, Pierre Hadot argued that despite all the
diversity in Hellenistic thought and all the various influences upon it from other
Mediterranean cultures, some common themes stand out. Firstly, philosophy is seen
as a spiritual path through which the philosopher holds himself aloof from ordinary
life. Moreover, the ideals and doctrines of the school will be embodied in the person
of the founder or sage who gives his name to that community. He will represent an
almost unattainable rational ideal and style of life, captured in the term, ‘wisdom’.
This is why philosophy seems strange to ordinary people. Thirdly, philosophers aim at
self-improvement and moral integrity through the control of distracting passions and
the acquisition of a virtuous character. The means towards these aims are meditation
on the doctrines of the school and on the physics of the universe, imaginative
unmasking of the illusory priorities of ordinary life, contemplation of death, dialogue
on these themes with others, and other structured exercises of reason. The goal of
theory is to serve practice: namely, the pursuit of serenity in the soul. There was little
critique of the school’s doctrines since they served as a means rather than as an
These facts present methodological difficulties for scholars. The written texts are a
secondary deposit left by an oral tradition of teaching, dialogue, and debate and this
makes exegesis of the extant ancient writings difficult. Much of classical philosophy
consisted of commentaries on the writings of the founders of various schools,
including Plato. So philosophy became a search for the authentic meaning of texts,
rather than for truth (although the latter was seen as the inner meaning of the texts).
The object of philosophical discourse is earlier philosophical discourse. This is a
theme to which Hadot returns when he suggests later that contemporary philosophy
A central theme of his book is that Hellenistic philosophical practice was focused on
what Hadot calls ‘spiritual exercises’ of which the goal is ‘a transformation of our
vision of the world, and a metamorphosis of our personality’ (82). The ancients used
these exercises to learn how to become free from the passions and the worries of daily
life, in the case of the Epicureans in order to enjoy the moment as something given by
chance, and in the case of the Stoics, as a duty lain upon one by one's place in the
cosmos. The Stoics argued that the ‘natural’ view of things (as opposed to the
‘human’ view) takes the universal and objective view and thus disabuses things of
their putative importance. Only the moral goods of life, of which we are the masters,
are relevant to our flourishing. Even the dialogues of Socrates are said to lead in this
direction. With all the variety in different schools, the method of these spiritual
exercises is common: namely, ‘the rhetorical and dialectical techniques of persuasion,
the attempts at mastering one’s inner dialogue, and mental concentration.’ (102)
Hadot suggests that the tradition of religious and monastic spiritual exercises of
Christianity stems from the ancient philosophers. But it was also Christianity which
came to rob philosophy of its role as a structure for such spiritual exercises. In
medieval times it became a mere provider of intellectual tools for doing theology.
And modern philosophy is heir to this intellectualist and desiccated tradition.
Hadot returns to this theme in his final chapter in which he stresses that philosophy
was and is a way of life. Real wisdom makes us be in a different way. Wisdom may be
unattainable, but it must be pursued so as to constitute our philosophical way of life.
Philosophy in this sense is therapeutic in that it brings peace of mind and inner
freedom through ‘cosmic consciousness’ (which, as I will explain below, is different
from an objective scientific worldview in that it involves seeing one’s own place in
the totality of things). “In order better to understand in what way ancient philosophy
could be a way of life, it is perhaps necessary to have recourse to the distinction
proposed by the Stoics, between discourse about philosophy and philosophy itself.”
(266) Living as a philosopher is not just applying a set of theorems to life, but a self-
transformation through the Stoic disciplines of physics, ethics, and logic. But the
modern tradition of philosophy has become a discourse about philosophy.
While the Stoics concentrated upon the purity of one’s intentions so as to bring one’s
individual will into conformity with universal reason, the Epicureans focused upon
the pleasure of existing. In either case the goal was to be attained by rigorous
intellectual work and attention to the present moment. Hadot disagrees with the
common image of the Hellenistic philosopher as one who withdraws from the world.
He thinks “there is an equilibrium – almost impossible to achieve – between the inner
peace brought about by wisdom, and the passions to which the sight of the injustices,
sufferings, and misery of mankind cannot help but give rise. Wisdom, however,
consists in precisely such an equilibrium, and inner peace is indispensable for
efficacious action.” (274) This is a theme to which we will see other of our authors
Hadot’s chapter seven discusses the Foucault of The Care of the Self and explains
how Hadot thinks Foucault interprets the ancients as focussing too much on the ‘self’
and not enough on the objective and universal aspects of nature and cosmic reason by
which we must guide our lives. Unlike Foucault, Hadot attributes a greater concern
for justice and service of the community to the Hellenistic philosophers.
Aesthetic considerations have a deep resonance in Hadot’s view. We should not
understand the ‘cosmic consciousness’ sought by the Stoics and others as an objective
or scientific form of understanding. Rather such ‘philosophical perception’ should be
seen as a form of aesthetic perception. Contemplation is not just a seeing of the world
objectively, but an objective seeing of our unity with the world. It is this which,
according to Seneca, requires an interior transformation of attitudes. And it is this
which shows that the Hellenistic philosophers should not be seen as being
preoccupied merely with an individualistic transformation of the self. Their concerns
were truly with the world and with reality as a whole.
Philosophical Counselling
For those who are inspired by de Botton to study philosophy in relation to the
question, How might philosophy help us live our lives more fully so as to attain
happiness? there are a few highly relevant contemporary studies which seek to
continue the discourses established by the ancients. These centre on the philosophical
practice called ‘philosophical counselling’.
Marinoff’s book offers a popular description of this practice. Whereas people used to
go to priests or therapists for problems of life, there is now philosophical counselling
available as well as group facilitation and organisational consulting. Marinoff explains
that such philosophical practices consist in finding relevant ideas from the great
philosophers (East or West) and applying them to the problem at hand, much in the
way that de Botton does. In this way, stress and confusion can be avoided and
guidance found. Marinoff explains that most counselling relationships are very short
term, with many comprising only one session. They help people to think more clearly
about their problems through the exchange of philosophical ideas with the counsellor.
Marinoff calls the process ‘therapy for the sane’. That is, it does not do the work of
psychotherapy or treat mental illness. Marinoff rejects the medicalisation of many life
problems at the hands of the psychotherapeutic community. Being based on science,
the approach of most psychotherapies is objective and causal and it is not obvious that
delving into the causes of one’s behaviour or concerns is always helpful in improving
the situation. Marinoff would reject the notion that self-knowledge gives us freedom.
Marinoff also critiques the medical model that is inherent in most psychological
therapies, with its proliferation of diagnostic categories, the reification of syndromes,
its seeming endlessness, and its irrelevance to everyday problems. Helping people
should not be based on science, says Marinoff. It is an art. It requires empathy rather
Marinoff presents an outline of his own five-step approach which he designates with
A Analyse, enumerate and evaluate the options available for solving the problem
C Contemplate your entire situation. Develop an integrated and objective view of
the problem and possible solutions. Draw on philosophical insights and
interpretations of such problems and adopt a philosophical attitude.
Having made a decision after the earlier stages, you reach Equilibrium and are
at peace with yourself and the solution you have come to. You are now ready to
act and to use the insights gained in this problem situation in other situations in
Marinoff illustrates this structure, and also argues how philosophical counselling
would differ from typical psychotherapy, by describing the case of Vincent who was
forced to remove a painting from his office wall because it gave offence to others.
Vincent was angry about this. Marinoff says that a psychotherapist would tackle this
anger as the problem, whereas a philosopher might help Vincent see and accept the
injustice of what happened to him. Moreover, Vincent is himself responsible for the
offence that he has taken at the incident and so for the anger he feels. Seeing this
allowed Vincent to stand back from the issue and get on with his life. Central to this
argument, which it only took one session to effect, was a distinction between harm
and offence that philosophers are trained to make. So it is clear thinking rather than
lengthy therapy can lead to a new equilibrium.
This form of practice draws insights and arguments from the tradition of philosophy
in order to apply them to present problems. Accordingly Marinoff presents an
extremely brief survey of philosophies and philosophers from Socrates through to the
existentialists and analytic philosophers in the Anglo-American tradition that
Marinoff suggests we will find useful in the ‘contemplation’ stage of his five-step
process. The survey includes some Eastern philosophers but is surprisingly silent on
the Hellenistic and Roman philosophers discussed by Hadot. Readers of de Botton
will recognise Seneca’s thinking in the Vincent case.
There are also some brief remarks of a more theoretical nature. Marinoff is grateful
for Descartes’ distinction between body and mind because it makes philosophical
counselling possible. If you have an illness or a problem that originates in your brain,
he suggests, you should see a doctor. But if it is a problem in your mind, then
philosophical counselling is apposite. There is considerable naivety in this view,
assuming, as it does, the completeness of the mind/body distinction, the transparency
of the mind, and the reality of free will as a function of the mind. Marinoff also
attributes to Hume a view that he finds very liberating: namely, the view that there is
‘no such thing as necessary cause; that we can’t establish a causal connection between
any two events.’ (65) He thinks that this implies that there is no predestination and
that anyone can change. Now while it is true that it will be liberating for anyone to
suppose that they can change, I doubt that one would need to deny the reality of
causality or adopt Hume’s essentially epistemological view on this matter in order to
yield this outlook. Marinoff’s interpretation of Hume is too brief to be enlightening
The greater worry for a book of this kind is the way in which, like de Botton,
Marinoff surveys a large number of philosophical ideas and picks up a few thoughts
that might be relevant to how we contemplate life without delving into the reasons
behind those views, the context in which they were developed, or whether they are
rationality justified. The reader is meant to just nod in agreement and apply the idea to
their own life. There is no invitation to consider whether the ideas are sound or not.
They are treated as if mentioning them in one or two sentences would be enough for
them to have an impact on our attitude to life. This chapter and the rest of the book are
liberally sprinkled with quotations from philosophers and, once again, one is put in
mind of desk calender aphorisms which are meant to do their edifying work by virtue
of their pithy cleverness, rather than by the thoroughness of the arguments of which
The next chapters present a number of cases to illustrate how philosophical
counselling works. So there is the case of Doug, the late night DJ, who does not have
anyone to love. Marinoff presents him with some insights from Lao Tzu and from
Buddha. But the upshot of these considerations is that there may be psychological
forces at play in Doug’s life of which he is not fully aware (perhaps he got the late
night job in order to avoid close contact with others). But if this is Marinoff’s
approach here, how does this differ from the pursuit of causes of which he accuses
psychotherapy? And what does it do to Descartes’ transparent self-knowledge? In
other cases, Marinoff adopts a strategy which he calls ‘bibliotherapy’, in which he and
the client study a relevant text together in order to find a solution to a problem and a
deeper attitude to it. (In the discussion of his cases, Marinoff only occasionally refers
back to the PEACE structure which he has described but, as he says that it is the
Contemplation and Equilibrium phases that are distinctive of philosophical
counselling, I assume that the introduction of philosophical sayings and texts are
intended to enrich these phases of the process.) But, once again, one does not see him
engaging in a deep philosophical dialogue using the text as stimulus material. Rather,
the text is mined for pithy aphorisms which may (or may not) inspire a change in
The case of Tonya, on the other hand, shows some real philosophy being done (but
Marinoff is not the counsellor in this case). Tonya is uneasy about the degree of
commitment required of her in her marriage. Discussion with her displays that she
understands ‘being committed to her relationship’ to mean having taken on
obligations and fulfilling the expectations of others. Here there is room for genuine
philosophical work which would consist in a conceptual and existential exploration of
what commitment is. And it was such work that led to a new and fruitful form of
In another case, the counsellor teaches the client to meditate in order that he might
break his habit of criticising his partner. How does this differ from many forms of
psychotherapy? More generally, the form that philosophical counselling takes is that
of finding a suitable quote or schema from any philosopher and applying it by analogy
to the case at hand. It is therapy by analogy. Just how apt the analogy is is never
discussed. The client’s problem is just made to fit the pattern of the philosopher’s
thinking: whether it be Hegel’s transcendence, Heraclitus’ view of the interaction of
opposites, Hobbes’ notion of the state of war, Buber’s I-Thou, and so on. Moreover,
the client is expected to see their own situation clearly through the prism of the
philosophy in question. Self-knowledge and philosophical understanding are both
assumed to be easy. One could ask why the philosophers are mentioned by name at
all. Does the client who is too self-giving need to be told about Ayn Rand in order that
she be convinced to give some thought to herself? What is added to that suggestion by
explaining that philosophy? Why not just point out the harm that this client is doing to
herself so that she will change her attitude and establish a new equilibrium. Is the
counsellor committing the fallacy of argument from authority?
What is striking as one reads the many brief case descriptions is that we never learn
what Marinoff’s philosophical commitments are. He has a philosophical bon mot for
every case, but we never know whether he believes them himself. Many of them are
inconsistent with each other. In one case we see him espousing both Kant’s and Ross’
conception of duty without seeming to notice that Ross’ notion of a prima facie duty
is at odds with Kant’s absolutism. Where is Marinoff coming from in his relationship
with his clients? Is he a philosopher with philosophical commitments and a dedication
to help others see the truth as he sees it? Or is he a collector of sayings with which he
can encourage and edify his clients but without any intellectual commitment on his
own part? Does he think there is a genuine good for each case derivable from some
general theory of the human good, or is he a postmodernist seeking only a particular
solution acceptable to a particular individual? Is he a consequentialist or a
deontologist? (He seems to be both.) He will even countenance the doctrine of
reincarnation if that helps a client to face life’s challenges. Will anything do, provided
it helps? To what extent is he giving his clients just and only what they want to hear?
Marinoff never defines what the ‘philosophical outlook’ is that he thinks clients
should attain. Is it a theory that is rationally worked through and justified, or is it just
a comforting attitude? The advice given by the ancients was backed up by
metaphysics. How valuable can advice be that does not have such a basis?
Marinoff also shows himself unaware of the social and economic contexts of his
clients. Many of them seem to have opportunities and possibilities that are denied to
those of more exigent means. That work should be creative in order to be satisfying is
a platitude not only because it requires analysis of its key terms but also because
creative work is not available to a vast number of people. It is striking that most of
Marinoff’s examples are of success stories. Given a little philosophical counselling,
Marinoff’s clients all go off and have beautiful relationships, success at work, and
meaningful lives. Nothing ever goes wrong once you have been touched by
philosophy. What about ‘permanent adversities’ such as bad luck or the evil that is
done to you by others? The most obvious manifestation of our powerlessness in
relation to reality is our own death. And here Marinoff takes on a much less confident
The modern practice of philosophical counselling was developed in recent times by
the German philosopher Gerd Achenbach and is continued today by members of the
International Society for Philosophical Practice which he founded. Shlomit Schuster’s
book describes the concept and methods of philosophical counselling that have been
developed within this recent tradition and raises a great many questions as to what,
precisely, philosophical counselling is. Using a medical metaphor, how does such
counselling differ from psychotherapy in all its many forms (including psychoanalysis
understood as a form of ‘talking cure’)? What are the methods of such counselling
that mark it off as distinctly philosophical?
After an historical survey of the practice, a wide ranging survey of writings about it,
and an exposition of its theory, Schuster’s answer to this last question is that
philosophical counselling is dialogical. It is a conversation. Indeed, following
Achenbach, Schuster insists that there is no method being followed in a counselling
session. Just as one does not follow a plan or a strategy in a conversation, so
philosophical counselling involves only a ‘method beyond method’. The impetus
behind this thought is the need to distinguish philosophical counselling from all forms
of psychiatry, psychoanalysis, psychotherapy, or other ‘treatments’ conceived on a
medical or therapeutic model. Inspired by elements of the anti-psychiatry movement
of the sixties, Schuster sees such therapeutic approaches as objectifying the client.
(Schuster refers to her own customers as ‘visitors’ rather than as ‘clients’). A therapist
produces a diagnosis. That is, he forms a theory about the client and about what the
unconscious or otherwise hidden causes of their problem might be. A therapist
interprets what a client says and the way she behaves in terms of categories of
pathology, and claims to have a better knowledge of the client’s motivations and
drives than does the client herself. In this way there is an inequality of power between
therapist and client. The therapist is an expert and the client becomes an object of
treatment. The ideal of philosophical counselling, in contrast, involves a mutuality
between counsellor and visitor as they engage in a conversation with salutary intent.
There is a very deep philosophical-anthropological commitment in such a practice
which Schuster fails to acknowledge fully. To express it in old fashioned terms, it
accords a higher place to free will than is customary in contemporary ways of
thinking. Under the influence of Freud, and such philosophical precursors of Freud as
Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, postmodern humanity is apt to think of itself as subject
to unconscious and instinctual drives as well as the formative – and sometimes
baneful – influences of society, upbringing, and circumstances. When we are unhappy
we tend to look for causes by interrogating the parenting we have received, the
partners we have chosen, or the job we have ended up in. And if things are not
immediately clear to us we might seek the help of psychiatrists or other
psychotherapists. The promise of such a practice is that by becoming clear on what is
causing our unhappiness, the hold of those causes upon us will be loosened and we
will be freed to pursue our authentic goals successfully. This is the promise of the
Schuster adheres to an older faith. Just as Socrates had held that explicit knowledge of
how to live one’s life would lead one to live well, so today’s philosophical counsellors
hold that by becoming articulate about the goals, ideals, and concerns of one’s life,
one will be able to live more effectively. What is the basis for this view? It is that
when we act – in a genuine sense of ‘act’ – we are motivated by reasons rather than
moved by causes. And we can take more control and accept more responsibility for
our lives when we are conscious of these reasons and when these reasons are, indeed,
rational and intelligent. Rather than seeing ourselves as subject to motivational forces
– a self-image that is antithetical to taking responsibility for one’s own life – Schuster
appeals to philosophers like Sartre to stress freedom and authenticity. An authentic
life is a Socratic life: that is, a life in which there is honest self-appraisal and rational
inquiry into goals. In short, an examined life. The role of philosophical counselling is
to engage in the kind of conversation with visitors which will allow those visitors to
attain to a greater degree of rational self-knowledge and responsible self-control.
This presents two problems. Firstly, the evaluation of the practice of philosophical
counselling depends upon a resolution of that most perennial of problems in
philosophical anthropology: namely, the nature of human freedom and responsibility.
It is a problem which, as the debate between Socrates and Aristotle over ‘weakness of
will’ shows, has been with us for a long time. And, as contemporary fascination with
such theories as sociobiology shows, it is far from resolved. Self-knowledge is
difficult to attain. Secondly, while there may be many people who have a requisite
degree of self-possession for living life in the light of good reasons and explicit
knowledge of what is good for living (whether that knowledge will have been attained
by their own study and reflection or with the help of conversations with a
philosophical counsellor), the unfortunate fact is that there are a great many people in
our society who find themselves unable to do what they want to do or know it is
good to do. The claustrophobic person may want to get into a lift and have a perfectly
well thought out reason for doing so. Yet he finds he cannot do it. Whom should he
consult: a philosophical counsellor who can help him clarify his reasons (and thereby,
perhaps, make them motivationally stronger), or a therapist who might successfully
expunge the phobia and so free the client to act as he wants to (assuming that the
therapy used is effective)? Is the difference here one of degree? Is there a range of
approaches with Rational-Emotive Behaviour Therapy (REBT) at one step removed
from philosophical counselling at one end, and electro-convulsive aversion therapy
along with milder forms of behaviour modification at the other? And where would
psychoanalysis be on such a spectrum? Schuster asserts that the difference is one of
type. For her, philosophical counselling is generically different in that it respects, and
seeks to enhance, the autonomy of the visitor.
But her reports of cases belie this assertion. Many of the cases that she describes in
the last third of her book are of problems that result from causes rather than bad
reasons. So one person is unable to sleep. Another engages in compulsive behaviour.
There is a case of eating disorder. Another has irrational feelings of guilt. There is a
case of a person with suicidal tendencies and another has nightmares. Many have been
in one form of therapy or another and found the experience unsatisfying. Schuster
frequently forms theories about her visitors and about what is wrong with them (how
is this not an objectifying diagnosis?). In the light of such theories, she often gives
advice. And she also admits that, often, salutary effects flow just from the visitor
having a chance to express their worries and feelings. Just how different is all this
from the less manipulative forms of psychotherapy? There are only a few cases where
the visitor is in need of a philosophical worldview in order to help make sense of life
and even then, rather than engage in dialogue, Schuster refers her to a philosopher
from the Western canon. She often gives visitors (even the ones whose problems have
unconscious causes) philosophical texts to read (sometimes quite difficult ones and
she does not report helping the visitor to understand them), or instructs them on the
ideas of relevant philosophers. In short, when a philosophical approach is taken it is
recognisable as philosophical only because of its content and not because of its
process. Whether she acknowledges it or not, Schuster is a therapist.
As with Marinoff, Schuster’s ‘method beyond method’ of counselling smacks of the
'aphorisms for sale' approach. There is no commitment to any one philosophical
position on her part and there is little attempt to teach visitors to do philosophy for
themselves. If it is therapy it should be based on psychological theory – and it isn't. If
it is philosophy it should respect the autonomy of the visitor and propound a coherent
Peter Raabe’s book is at once more thorough and more effective in identifying a
distinctive practice of philosophical counselling. Based on a PhD thesis, the text
begins with an exhaustive survey of an extensive literature in which forms of
counselling that either explicitly or implicitly claim to be philosophical in some sense
are described and, in many cases critiqued. About the only field missing from Raabe’s
survey is that of pastoral care which would have provided an interesting comparison,
especially since he does discuss cases of group sessions in prisons which have
rehabilitative aims. Themes that emerge are that the aims of philosophical counselling
are to help clients (Raabe does not use the term ‘visitor’) come to know themselves
and to understand their lives better by philosophical means. It concerns questions
about the meaning of life and other existential themes and seeks to fill the void left in
our spiritual lives by the cultural eclipse of religion. Insofar as our emotions and
attitudes are as important to such aims as our reasoning, it does not just confine itself
to logic and critical rationality. It is client centred and seeks to explore, critique, or
ground the client’s worldview through dialogue. It aims to assist clients achieve
authenticity in self-knowledge and action. The counsellor is said to be using
hermeneutic techniques of understanding and to encourage the client to apply
phenomenological forms of thought to their self-understanding.
Raabe discovers a great many methods used by various counsellors which draw on a
bewildering variety of philosophers and psychologists. He also distinguishes specific
techniques and strategies, some, like Marinoff’s, involving stages or steps in definite
procedures. He agrees with those who reject the ‘beyond method’ approach arguing
that for an incipient profession to adopt an ‘anything goes’ approach would be for it to
jeopardise its credibility. Raabe devotes an entire chapter to the dialectic between
philosophical counselling and psychotherapy in its many forms. He agrees that it
differs from psychoanalysis which seeks causes of which the client is unconscious,
but points to other forms of psychotherapy, such as REBT, existential therapy, and
logotherapy, to which it bears similarities. Indeed, he questions whether the
distinction is sustainable, especially since many forms of psychotherapy involve the
‘intentional stance’ towards clients (seeing them as autonomous and acting on
reasons) that is central to philosophical counselling. So once again, what is
distinctively philosophical about this practice? Perhaps, given the expectations with
which clients come to philosophical counselling, this practice ought to be
acknowledged as being therapeutic in the modern sense.
In the central section of the book, Raabe offers a four-stage method or process which
should mark philosophical counselling at its best. While not every period of
counselling with a client may involve all four stages and may not need to, an ideal and
complete program would. Raabe suggests that the various aspects of these four stages
exemplify what other writers on philosophical counselling have seen as its central
feature. In this way his model combines what is best in many other accounts. The first
stage is called ‘Free-Floating’ and consists in the client expressing their problems and
feelings while the counsellor listens carefully and sensitively but with a minimum of
interruption or direction. As Schuster had noted in some of her cases, giving clients
the opportunity to unburden themselves of their concerns or questions can have a
salutary effect in itself. This stage is exploratory for both client and counsellor in that
the former can explore what the process involves while the latter can judge (but
without forming a diagnosis) whether the case is amenable to the philosophical
counselling approach. This stage may last for several sessions of one hour as both
parties move towards a deeper understanding of the situation or concern of the client.
Insofar as the counsellor contributes, it is to offer reassurance. Raabe suggests that
this stage echoes Achenbach’s and Schuster’s ‘method beyond method’.
The second stage is that of ‘Immediate Problem Resolution’. It is at this stage that
philosophical counselling is most like psychotherapy. The client might have problems
making a difficult decision, or be inhibited in life by barely understood personality
factors. There may be a moral dilemma, or a lack of understanding of what is
important in a situation. At this stage, the counsellor does indeed act as an expert and
seeks to guide the client (by Socratic rational argument used to uncover
misconceptions, in the example that Raabe offers) to a solution to the problem. That
said, it remains true that the solution must be genuinely discovered by the client and
not just offered by the counsellor. At this stage, the counsellor works within the
worldview of the client (in his example, Raabe does not challenge his client’s
religious beliefs) so as to uncover a solution that the client can immediately accept.
The progress towards the solution should be rationally grounded by logical steps in
premises and assumptions that are already in place. The counsellor should use no
rhetorical means of persuasion such as would allow the client later to suppose that he
had been conned. Many clients leave counselling after the successful completion of
But the third stage begins to highlight the distinctly philosophical nature of
philosophical counselling. It is the stage of Teaching as an Intentional Act. Having
left the immediate problem behind the counsellor now seeks to impart the skills of
logical and critical thinking that had allowed that solution to emerge so that the client
can, in future, deal with such puzzles on their own. Raabe notes that many writers on
philosophical counselling espouse this goal but do not display it in their practice.
They seem to assume that having gone through a rational process the client will just
pick up those skills implicitly. Raabe sees philosophical counselling as teaching. One
directly relevant way of approaching this will be to review stage two after the event
and uncover the intellectual moves that had been made in it. But it is not only logic
that is involved here. There should also be theoretical discussion of emotions and
other personality factors that enter into the living of life. This stage should be
productive of insight. Perhaps the practice of Socrates exemplifies this stage insofar
as, when it succeeds, it empowers the client to live life with self-sufficiency.
Long term clients may want to proceed to the fourth stage of the philosophical
counselling process: namely, ‘Transcendence’. It is here that the client is led to see
themselves and their lives in the context of a larger whole, whether it be society, the
world at large, or a religious conception. This stage seems to echo Marinoff’s
‘Contemplation’ and ‘Equilibrium’ stages. At this stage there is discussion of the
adequacy of world-views and there may be challenges to the conceptions that do not
hold up to rational scrutiny. The counsellor is not seeking to impose his own views,
but he is teaching the client to think critically about their own and to discover the
standards and criteria of acceptability for such views. Here the goal is to be as
objective as possible and to do philosophy. Here the client is developing their own
theory about life and the world. Raabe does not say so at this point, but I would
imagine that at this stage it might be appropriate to give the client short texts to read
between sessions and then to discuss them. This would be more than just providing a
few thought provoking epigrams or aphorisms because attention would be drawn to
the arguments in the text. I also imagine that it may also be appropriate to pursue the
aims of this stage of philosophical counselling in the form of well structured Socratic
Dialogue group sessions. Raabe makes the important point that this and the previous
stage of philosophical counselling are proactive and preventive in the life of the client
in that they ground her rational autonomy. I imagine that the nature of the counsellor-
client relationship becomes quite difficult at this point. The counsellor has taken on
the role of a teacher but, like all good teachers, will need to take care to both introduce
new and challenging ideas while still respecting the ideas and worldviews that the
client already evinces. The counsellor must not impose his views or disparage those of
the client while still bringing the client to new understandings and, perhaps, to a
It is these last two stages of philosophical counselling that makes it distinctly
philosophical. They also account for the insistence of many in the philosophical
counselling movement that only trained philosophers should be engaged in
philosophical counselling. This point is also relevant to the question of what sort of
training is appropriate for a philosophical counsellor. This is an issue that is being
hotly debated within the profession, with Schuster leading the faction that would
eschew formal training and Marinoff heading the faction that would insist on training
and accreditation. If Raabe is right to suggest that there is no deep difference between
philosophical counselling and certain forms of psychotherapy, and if Schuster’s cases,
many of whom require therapy, are typical, then it would seem to me that a
philosophical counsellor should first be a trained therapist. It will be necessary for the
sake of the first and second stages of the process that they be trained or experienced as
therapists and it will be necessary for the sake of the third and fourth stages of the
process that they be highly competent as philosophers and as teachers of philosophy.
There is much to be learnt for counselling from the Western tradition of philosophy.
Philosophy is more than just intellectual skill. It also contains content that will help us
live our lives well. And this is not just content in the form of inspirational aphorisms
and edifying sayings. Such content could be conveyed by anyone with a good
dictionary of quotations. Philosophy also gives us a form of thinking which enhances
our lives through protecting us from prejudice and error, deepening our
understanding, and enlarging our vision through our own thinking. Accordingly, to
help someone live their lives well requires that one teaches them to do philosophy
rather than just conveying insights from philosophers. And this in turn requires that
the counsellor be a philosopher in the fullest sense of that term.
The final section of the book contains a number of case studies which amply illustrate
what has gone before. We learn from these that Raabe does give his clients apposite
essays to read between sessions (and thereby indicates that counsellors should be sure
to equip themselves with a wide range of reading both within and outside of
philosophy). He also asks clients to write between sessions on occasion. I would
imagine that their keeping a more formal journal would also be of use. Raabe also
describes group sessions using both Leonard Nelson’s ‘Socratic Dialogue’ method
and Matthew Lipman’s ‘Community of Inquiry’.
The fourth of Raabe’s stages is of special interest to me because of my own view of
what makes a practice distinctively philosophical. Taking my inspiration from
Aristotle’s four-part analysis of human functioning (designated by him as ‘parts of the
soul’), I place great importance on the contemplative function which he distinguished
from the calculative function. We use the latter when we plan, think logically, and
intelligently order our lives, and when we act with forethought, insight, and prudence.
But our lives are not complete when we live well at this level of our being. We also
have a deep need for seeing ourselves within a larger world-view. Religion meets this
need by placing our lives within the context of a theological story. Some political
ideologies do it by placing our lives into a context of an historical trajectory. And I am
impressed by the view that the quest for justice provides such a framework. Whatever
form it takes, some larger view of this kind is a spiritual need that we all have and
which both Plato and Aristotle thought grounded a fully happy life. Philosophy (along
with theology, theoretical physics, art, politics, and possibly other human cultural
forms) answers to this need. Accordingly, any counselling process that calls itself
philosophical must go beyond offering pragmatic or therapeutic help to people. It
must take them to what Raabe has called a level of transcendence. And this does not
mean that it must teach metaphysical doctrines. Rather it means that it must
inaugurate a form of thinking which enters the domain which classical philosophy has
opened up to us. We must develop what Hadot calls an aesthetic perception of our
Conclusion
The ancient inscription in Delphi, ‘Know Thyself’, and Socrates’ claim that ‘The
unexamined life is not worth living’, have given rise to important traditions within
western philosophy. Under the influence of the enlightenment and the individualism
of modern life, this has become a quest for fulfilment in life through thinking
philosophically. What this has meant includes knowing oneself truly and living in
accordance with that knowledge so as to achieve integrity and authenticity. It has also
meant seeing oneself in the context of a larger whole, whether that be the cosmos,
nature, history, or society, and living in accordance with that conception so as to
achieve an ethical life. Contemporary philosophers are also beginning to see that it
involves living in dialogue with others so as to create community and a less
individualistic form of ethical self-knowledge. But in all cases it means using the
methods of reason and argument in order to clarify thinking, avoid self-deception and
superstition, and develop a warrantable world-view.
In what way are these practices distinctively philosophical? Is rational process
enough? Or is there a content which may be called wisdom? The quest to know
oneself and to achieve authenticity urges us to transcend the distortive layers of
culture and causality upon our being and to become true to our true self. The quest to
understand the cosmos and reality as it is in itself is similarly an attempt to transcend
the distortive layers of culture and tradition upon our knowledge of reality. Perhaps
these two quests are one and the same. It may be that the spiritual exercises or the
‘care of the self’ that Socrates inaugurated with his dialogical style of life lead
inevitably to the seeking of a ‘cosmic consciousness’, or an ‘aesthetic perception’, in
which one achieves, through contemplation, a world-view and a self-conception
marked by equilibrium and transcendence. It is only in modern times that the self that
enters the dialogue, asks the philosophical questions, and is itself in question has been
interpreted so individualistically. Perhaps in these postmodern times we will find
ourselves when we stop looking for ourselves or seeking self-control and
acknowledge the greater realities of which we are a part.
Clinical course of sepsis in children with acute leukemia admitted to the pediatric intensive care unit* Kanakadurga Singer, MD, MA; Perla Subbaiah, PhD; Raymond Hutchinson, MD;Folafoluwa Odetola, MD, MPH; Thomas P. Shanley, MD Objective: To describe the clinical course, resource use, and inotropic and/or vasopressor drugs ( p ؍ .01), and renal replace- mortality of patients wi
International symposium Angola on the Move: Transport Routes, Communication and History, The copyright for this paper lies solely with the author. Any further circulation requires his or her personal permission (see addresses under [participants --> contributors --> contact list]) as well as full and accurate attribution to the author, Symposium and web location. Angola: Movimentos mi